The tragic man
“In
this world only play, play as artists and children engage in it, exhibits
coming-to-be and passing away, structuring and destroying... And as children
and artists play, so plays the ever living fire. It constructs and destroys,
all in innocence... Transforming itself into water and earth, it builds towers
of sand like a child at the seashore, piles them up and tramples them down...
The ever self-renewing impulse to play calls new worlds into being. The child
throws its toys away from time to time - and starts again in innocent caprice.
But when it does build, it combines and joins and forms its structures regularly,
conforming to inner laws.”
(Nietzche)
In unveiling
narcissism as a powerful undercurrent of human experience, Freud pointed to the
similarities among the megalomania of the schizophrenic, the magical thinking
of "primitive" (non-Western) people, the blind infatuation of the
lover, and the "childish," doting adulation of parents toward their
offspring. The common element in these states, Freud argued, is
"overvaluation"-whatever is being considered, whether in oneself or
in another, is inflated in importance, its powers exaggerated, its unique perfections
extolled. The narcissistic overvaluations of the schizophrenic, the primitive,
the lover, the parent, are all secondary derivatives of a more fundamental
narcissistic condition, Freud argued, which constitutes the earliest stage of
psychic development. Freud portrays the state of primary narcissism as one of
total omnipotence, perfection, completeness. The infant imagines himself as
constituting the entire universe, or certainly all that is good and pleasurable
in it.
Illusion as
Defense
Although the
state of primary narcissism cannot be maintained for long in a world of
inevitable frustrations and increasing parental expectations, the original
narcissistic experience, in Freud's view, is not wholly renounced. Much of
narcissistic libido is transformed into object libido, self-gratification
replaced by drive gratifications facilitated by others as libidinal objects.
Some of the original narcissism remains intact, however, and self-regard
derives from three different forms in which narcissistic libido is preserved.
Some primary
narcissism simply remains from its original state and serves, like the
protoplasmic body of the amoeba, as a never-wholly emptied pool of libidinal
resources from which pseudopodlike object libidinal cathexes are drawn. Sometimes
narcissistic libido is transferred to the sexual object; here the object is not
loved in an anaclitic way, modeled after those who provided drive
gratifications, but in an idealized, narcissistic fashion, modeled after the
inflated self-love of primary narcissism. Some narcissistic libido is set up
within the ego ideal. Self-rapture in relation to the child's true attributes
is no longer possible; but if the parents' values and expectations can be
fulfilled, wholeness and perfection are once again attainable.
The common
feature in these three vicissitudes of narcissistic libido is
"overvaluation," which Freud identifies as the "narcissistic
stigma" (1914b, p. 91). Whether the focus is actually oneself, one's
wished-for self, or the beloved, the object is granted positive qualities
beyond what is supportable by reality. Thus narcissism in Freud’s system
entails the attribution of illusory value. His metaphor of the amoeba and its
oscillatory protoplasm, now extending outward into the world, now retreating
backward into the central body, highlights the· reciprocal relationship he saw
between engagement with reality (and other people) and narcissistic illusions.
For Freud, narcissistic illusions (even when they are transferred through
idealization onto love objects), ultimately draw one away from real
involvements with others and the gratifications they provide.
Although an
explorer of the darkest, most irrational dimensions of human experience, Freud
was a supreme rationalist in his sense of social, moral, and scientific values.
Rationality, fueled by sublimation, represents the highest and most felicitous
development of the human mind. The discontents we suffer in civilization are
the necessary price of its uplifting advantages. Unless impeded by neurosis,
developmental progress is characterized by a movement from primary process to
secondary process, from the pleasure principle to the reality principle.
Psychoanalysis as a treatment facilitates this process whereby the irrational
and fantastic is brought under the sway of the rational and the real -
"where id was, there ego shall be" (1933, p. 80).
Kaplan (1985)
has described Freud's dedication to rationality in striking terms.
“If people must
suffer the loss of their infantile hopes and fantasies, then they should suffer
for the fact of this loss rather than for distortions of it in aesthetic
bonuses, the empty promises of religion, and the negligible protections of
social orders. Unremitting toil in the service of science - naked means toward
real ends - was Freud's (1930/1961) alternative in Civilization and Its
Discontents, at least for himself. Any other kind of life was ensnared by
illusion, which was but a small step up from neurosis. (pp. 290-291)
In this larger
context, Freud regarded narcissistic illusions as the inevitable residue of the
most primitive and infantile state of mind, and therefore as both unavoidable
and dangerous. Precisely because narcissism, by definition, entails illusory
overvaluation, it runs counter to reality and beckons as an ever-tempting
defensive retreat. Withdrawal from reality is always perilous, the ultimate
threat being the total loss of connection with the real world (the
schizophrenic state) and the less devastating threat posed by the vulnerable
loss of self, suffered by the unrequited lover, whose narcissism is transferred
to the beloved and never returned.
Freud's stress
on the defensive function of illusions has been largely maintained in what one
might consider the mainstream of contemporary Freudian thought, although
exactly what is being defended against varies in different accounts, depending
on the larger set of theoretical premises which shape that account. Let us
consider, as examples of the traditional approach to illusion as defense, two
of the most significant recent contributions to the literature on narcissism
from within Freudian ego psychology, those of Kernberg and Rothstein.
Although
Kernberg stresses his loyalties to Mahler, Jacobson, and the ego-psychological
tradition, his contributions draw extensively on Melanie Klein's model of
mental life, and his approach to narcissistic illusion is greatly informed by her
theories. Klein portrays the infant as beset with terrifying anxieties
involving the containment of aggression, and sees early development as a
movement from paranoid and depressive anxieties toward a more integrated and
secure sense of reality. Within Klein's vision, narcissistic illusions operate
as defenses and regressive retreats from these frightening early anxieties:
idealization is a refuge from persecutory anxiety and murderous rage toward bad
objects; grandiosity is a "manic" defense against the depressive
anxiety inherent in feeling small, helpless, and abjectly dependent upon
another. Kernberg borrows heavily from these conceptualizations.
He distinguishes
normal from pathological narcissism, defining the former (following Freud, as
amended by Hartmann, 1950, p. 127) as the libidinal investment of the self.
What Kernberg means by normal narcissism, then, is the resultant of all the
processes which bear on self-representation and self-regard. He sees
pathological narcissism as a particular dynamic mechanism which generates both
entitled grandiosity and primitive idealization. Following Klein, Kernberg
characterizes these as primitive defense mechanisms, often operating in
conjunction with other primitive defense mechanisms such as splitting, denial,
and projective identification. Narcissistic illusions are a defense erected
within the child's struggle with a "pathologically augmented development
of oral aggression" (1975, p. 234), generating paranoid and depressive
anxieties; the illusions are constructed from a pathological fusion of ideal
self, ideal object, and actual self-image.
How do
narcissistic illusions work? In Kernberg's account, the infant is overloaded
with primitive aggressive impulses, due to a "constitutionally determined
strong aggressive drive, or constitutionally determined lack of anxiety
tolerance in regard to aggressive impulses, or severe frustration in their first
year of life" (1975, p. 234). He experiences himself and, projectively,
other people as well, as essentially sadistic, and this aggressive outlook
dominates his early experience. Sticking close to Klein's account of
"envy" (1957), Kernberg portrays the narcissistically prone infant as
so frustrated and hateful as to be unable to tolerate hope, the possibility of
anyone's offering him anything pleasurable or sustaining. So little is
forthcoming, the child concludes, and with such ill will toward him, that it is
better to expect nothing, to want nothing, to spoil and devalue everything that
might be offered. Normal fantasies of self and other as ideal are fused with
the child's own realistic self-perceptions, resulting in a ‘grandiose self'
which is experienced as complete, perfect, and self-sustaining. "I am/have
everything. You are/offer nothing." This position serves as both an
expression of and a defense against explosive oral aggression, and the only
secure solution in a world experienced as treacherous and sinister. Maintenance
and protection of the grandiose self becomes the central psychodynamic motive,
resulting in a contemptuous character style and disdainful manner of relating
to others.
“A narcissistic
patient experiences his relationships with other people as being purely
exploitative, as if he were "squeezing a lemon and then dropping the
remains." People may appear to him either to have some potential food
inside, which the patient has to extract, or to be already emptied and therefore
valueless.” (1975, p. 233)
Primitive
idealization of others is also characteristic of personalities organized around
a grandiose self, according to Kernberg, but the idealization has little to do
with any real valuing of others. Rather, Kernberg's narcissistic patient
projects his own grandiose self-image onto others when it becomes impossible to
sustain within himself, and also uses idealization as a secondary defense,
along with splitting, to ward off and conceal the hateful and contemptuous
devaluation of others.
Thus,
narcissistic illusions protect the patient from the dreadful state in which he
spent much of the first several years of life, depending on others for
protection and care, yet perpetually dissatisfied, victimized, and enraged. The
establishment of the grandiose self removes the patient from the multifaceted
psychic pain of this situation, and, once established, the grandiose self
perpetuates the devaluing assumptions about others which made its establishment
necessary in the first place. It creates a "vicious circle of
self-admiration, depreciation of others, and elimination of all actual
dependency. The greatest fear of these patients is to be dependent on anybody
else, because to depend means to hate, envy, and expose themselves to the
danger of being exploited, mistreated, and frustrated" (Kernberg, 1975, p.
235).
Narcissistic
illusions have a perniciously sabotaging effect on psychoanalytic treatment.
Based on the illusions of self-sufficiency and perfection of the grandiose
self, they undercut the very basis on which the psychoanalytic process rests,
the presumption that the analysand might gain something meaningful from someone
else (in this case the analyst). Despite what might be considerable psychological
suffering and a genuine interest in treatment, the analysand whose character is
organized around a grandiose self cannot allow the analyst to become important enough
to him to really help him. The analyst and his interpretations must be
continually devalued, spoiled, to avoid catapulting the patient into a
condition of overpowering longing, abject dependency, and intolerable hatred
and envy.
Kernberg's
technical recommendations are wholly consistent with this psychodynamic
portrait-a methodical and persistent interpretation of the defensive function
of grandiosity and idealization as they emerge in the transference (1984, p.
197). Anything else is a waste of time, since the narcissistic illusions
systematically destroy the very ground upon which the treatment proceeds.
Unless the workings of the grandiose self are continually brought to light and
confronted, the impact of the treatment is often subtly but systematically
vitiated. "The analyst must continuously focus on the particular quality
of the transference in these cases and consistently counteract the patient's
efforts toward omnipotent control and devaluation" (1975, p. 246). This
traditional emphasis on aggressive interpretation of narcissistic phenomena
derives from and is wholly consistent with Freud's early view of
"narcissistic neurosis" as unanalyzable and narcissistic defenses as
generating the most recalcitrant resistances to the analytic process. (See, for
example, Abraham, 1919.)
Rothstein (1984)
has presented a rich amalgam of dynamic formulations which he portrays as an
"evolutionary" extension of Freud's structural model (from which he
has deleted virtually all energic considerations). The result is a
psychodynamic account which stresses conflict among various relational motives
and puts particular stress on the importance of the actual relationship to
significant others. The most pervasive influence on Rothstein's perspective,
particularly with regard to more severe disorders, is Mahler's depiction of the
process of separation-individuation from an original symbiotic matrix. Rothstein's
approach to narcissism is a blend of Freud's original formulations and Mahler's
more contemporary view of the child's struggle for relational autonomy.
Rothstein
distinguishes Freud's phenomenological portrayal of narcissism as a "felt
quality of perfection" from his metapsychological treatment of narcissism
(as the libidinal cathexis of the ego). He adds symbiosis to Freud's account of
primary narcissism and sees narcissistic illusions as based developmentally on
pre individuated experiences of a perfect self fused with a perfect object. The
loss of this original state of perfection is a severe narcissistic blow, an
inevitable developmental insult which is traversed only by reinstating the lost
narcissistic perfection in the ego ideal. By identifying with the
narcissistically tinged images of the ego ideal, the child softens the
otherwise unbearable pain of separation. "Narcissistically invested
identification is the sole condition under which the id can give up its objects
and is a fundamental concomitant of primary separation-individuation. The
pursuit of narcissistic perfection in one form or another is a defensive
distortion that is a ubiquitous characteristic of the ego" (Rothstein,
1983, p. 99).
Thus, like
Freud, Rothstein sees some residues of primary narcissism as inevitable,
reestablished in the ego ideal. For Rothstein, with his Mahlerian perspective,
the loss of infantile narcissism has an additional poignancy, since it
represents not just the loss of grandeur and perfection, but the loss of the
original symbiotic state. Accordingly, narcissistic illusions operate as
defensive retreats not only from disappointments in reality in general, but
also from anxiety and dread connected with separation. He holds that
"narcissistic perfection is a defensive distortion of reality" (p.
98). Like many defenses within the ego-psychological model, narcissism itself
is neither healthy nor pathological; some defenses are necessary and serve
adaptive functions within the psychic economy. Although a total relinquishment
of narcissistic illusions is impossible, it is the goal of analysis, in
Rothstein's view, to identify and work through the salient narcissistic
investments.
Although
proceeding from a very different set of basic assumptions concerning the
motivational and structural underpinnings of emotional life, the major
theorists within the interpersonal tradition have taken an approach to the
clinical phenomenon of illusions, the implications of which are quite similar
to the mainstream Freudian approach from Freud to Kernberg to Rothstein. Sullivan
sees idealization as a dangerous, self-depleting security operation and stresses
the "cost" to the patient of "thinking the doctor is wonderful"
(White, 1952, p. 134). He recommends challenging the patient's assumptions that
the analyst is so different from other people, often a product ofinexperience
in taking risks with others, and sees extended periods ofidealization as
reflecting a kind of acting out of countertransference. "The effective
restriction of idealization is dependent on the physician's own freedom from
personality warp. In so far as he is capable of real intimacy in the situation
with the patient, to that extent he can inhibit idealization... The measure
of this capacity [is] intuited or empathized by any patient" (Sullivan,
1972, p.343).
Similarly,
Sullivan regards grandiosity as a dynamic for covering over feelings of
insecurity through "invidious comparison" between oneself and others,
“an accelerating spiral of desperate attempts to prop up a steadily undermined security,
with the result that the patient is more and more detested and avoided… If the
patient will be alert to how small he feels with anybody who seems to be at all
contented or successful in any respect, then he may not have need for this
hateful superiority-which is hateful in part because he hates himself so much,
being unable to be what he claims to be.” (quoted in White, 1952, p. 139)
Although
Sullivan does not develop an explicit technical procedure for the handling of
illusions, one gets the clear impression throughout his writings that the
analyst is in no way helpful by failing to address the patient's overvaluation
of either himself or the analyst. Both kinds of illusions are seen as
self-sabotaging devices propping up a shaky sense of self-esteem, operating as
an obstacle to the development of the analysand's own resources and
self-respect.
Fromm takes an
even dimmer view of the place of illusion in emotional life. He sees
psychodynamics in the general context of certain inescapable realities of the
human condition, among which are finitude and separateness. To this condition
two kinds of responses are possible: progressive, productive responses which
accept the existential realities and create meaningful ties to others; and regressive,
destructive responses, based on a self-deluding denial of the realities of the
human condition. The overvaluing of illusions concerning the self or others
from whom one derives some compensatory reassurance are regressive
self-deceptions from Fromm's perspective and must be dealt with as such. In
fact, at several points Fromm accuses Sullivan, in his emphasis on protecting
the analysand's need for security, of being in effect soft on illusions.
Anything short of a continual interpretive challenge to the analysand's
overvaluing illusions concerning both himself and the analyst would be an
expression of countertransferential contempt on the analyst's part, a
disrespectful collusion in the analysand's flight from reality and meaning.
Thus, although deriving
from very different psychodynamic traditions and assumptions, the major lines
of theorizing within orthodox theory, Freudian ego psychology, and
interpersonal theory all converge in an essentially similar technical approach
to the clinical phenomenon of narcissistic illusions. The latter are viewed as
regressive defenses against frustration, separation, aggression, dependence,
and despair. Transferential illusions concerning either the self or the analyst
must be interpreted, their unreality pointed out, and their defensive purpose
defined.
Illusion as
Creativity
In recent years
there has emerged an alternative view of infantile mental states and the
narcissistic illusions which are thought to derive from them. This approach is
closely connected with the developmental-arrest model of psychopathology and
the therapeutic action of psychoanalytic treatment. The most important
contributors to this very different perspective have been Winnicott and Kohut,
each of whom in his own distinct fashion regards infantile narcissism and
subsequent narcissistic illusions in later life as the core of the self and the
deepest source of creativity. Here the prototypical "narcissist" is
not the child, madman, or savage, but the creative artist, drawing for
inspiration on overvaluing illusions.
Although
Winnicott did not often write about narcissism per se, his entire opus revolves
around the issue which we have seen is central to that domain: the relationship
between illusion and reality, between the self and the outside world. For
Winnicott, the key process in early development is the establishment of a sense
of the self experienced as real. For this to happen, the child requires a very
particular sort of relationship with his or her providers, the most
distinguishing feature of which is, ironically, that the child must not know of
the existence of the relationship, must not know that it is being provided at
all.
The essential
feature ofthe necessary "facilitating" environment provided by the
mother is her effort to shape the environment around the child's spontaneously
arising wishes, to read the child's needs and provide for them. The mother's
actualization of the infant's desires makes it possible for the latter to
assume that his wishes actually create the objects of his desire - that the
breast, in effect his entire world, is the product of his creation. In fact,
Winnicott characterizes the child's experience, made possible by the mother's
perfect accommodation to his wishes, as the "moment of illusion." The
virtual invisibility of Winnicott's "good enough mother" allows the
infant a developmentally crucial immersion in an illusory, megalomaniacal,
solipsistic state of "subjective omnipotence."
Eventually the
child learns to live in objective reality (introduced largely through the
mother's incremental failure to accommodate herself to the child's wishes) as
it becomes clear that objects and people have their own independent existence
and are only minimally under the child's control. The distinguishing
characteristic of the terrain between the original subjective omnipotence and
the eventual objective reality, transitional experiencing, is an ambiguity
about the status of the other. Is the transitional object (the traditional
teddy bear, for example) a creation of the child, in some special relation to the
child, under his or her control, or is it simply an object within the world of
mundane objects, subject to being lost, damaged, discarded, washed? The
good-enough parent of the transitional stage allows the child this ambiguity,
participating in the child's illusions like the mother whose accommodation
makes possible the earlier experience of subjective omnipotence, thereby enabling
the child to solidify a sense of self as a consistent source of spontaneous
wishes, longings, and resources.
Freud measured
mental health in terms of the capacity to love and work; Winnicott envisions
health as the capacity for play, as freedom to move back and forth between the
harsh light of objective reality and the soothing ambiguities of lofty
self-absorption and grandeur in subjective omnipotence. In fact, Winnicott
regards the reimmersion into subjective omnipotence as the ground of
creativity, in which one totally disregards external reality and develops one's
illusions to the fullest. He originally presented his view of patients with
fragmented, aborted (false) selves as a distinct diagnostic group reflecting
more severe psychopathology and, employing the developmental tilt, he placed
them developmentally as antedating oedipal neuroses. As is often the case with
theoretical innovations introduced through the establishment of a new
diagnostic category, the category spreads and the formulations take on more and
more general relevance. Thus, many varieties of psychopathology came to be viewed
by Winnicott as reflecting deficiencies in the establishment of a healthy self,
as a consequence of insufficient experience of the illusions of subjective
omnipotence and the transitional phase.
This view of the
development of the self led Winnicott to redefine both the analytic situation
and the analytic process. Whereas Freud saw the analytic situation in terms of
abstinence (instinctual wishes emerge and find no gratification), Winnicott
sees the analytic situation in terms of satisfaction, not of instinctual
impulses per se, but of crucial developmental experiences, missed parental
functions. The couch, the constancy of the sessions, the demeanor of the
analyst these become the "holding environment" which was not provided
in infancy. Freud saw the analytic process in terms of renunciation; by
bringing to light and renouncing infantile wishes and illusions, healthier and
more mature forms of libidinal organization become possible. Winnicott sees the
analytic process in terms of a kind ofrevitalization; the frozen, aborted self
is able to reawaken and begin to develop as crucial ego needs are met.
Although
Winnicott does not apply this model of treatment to the problem of narcissistic
illusions per se, its implications are clear. The patient's self has been
fractured and crushed by maternal impingement, creating the necessity for a
premature adaptation to external reality and a disconnection from one's own
subjective reality, the core of the self and the source of all potential
creativity. The analyst's task is to fan the embers, to rekindle the spark. He
must create an atmosphere as receptive as possible to the patient's
subjectivity; he must avoid challenging the patient in any way which could be
experienced as an impingement, an insistence once again on compliance with
respect to external reality. Narcissistic illusions, in Winnicott's model, are
neither defenses nor obstructions. The patient's illusions concerning both
himself and the analyst represent the growing edge of the patient's aborted
self; as good-enough mothering entails an accommodation of the world to sustain
the infant's illusions, good-enough analysis entails an accommodation of the
analytic situation to the patient's subjective reality, a "going to meet
and match the moment of hope" (1945, p. 309).
The more
explicit technical implications of this new understanding of the meaning of
narcissistic illusions were developed by Kohut, who, like Winnicott, introduced
his innovations in connection with a diagnostic category of greater severity
(narcissistic personality disorders), but who expanded those innovations into a
broad and novel theory of development, psychic structure, and motivation. In
his original 1971 presentation Kohut described two forms of transference, the
mirroring transference and the idealizing transference, which, he argued, are
very different from ordinary neurotic transferences. Here the patient is not
simply transferring infantile impulses and conflicts onto the person of the
analyst as a differentiated object. In the mirroring and idealizing
transferences, the analyst and his responses function in lieu of missing
psychic structures within the patient's own personality. In mirroring
transference the patient experiences himself in terms of overvaluing
grandiosity and requires the analyst's mirroring responses to avoid a
disintegration of self. In idealizing transference the patient experiences the
analyst in terms of overvaluing admiration and requires the analyst's allowance
of the idealization to avoid a disintegration of self.
In Kohut's
account, the appearance of narcissistic illusions within the analytic
situation-primitive grandiosity or idealization-represents the patient's
attempt to establish crucial developmental opportunities, a self-object
relationship unavailable in childhood. These phenomena represent not a
defensive retreat from reality (a la Freud, Sullivan, Rothstein, and Kernberg),
but the growing edge of an aborted developmental process which was stalled
because of parental failure to allow the child sustained experiences of
illusions of grandeur and idealization. Thus, the appearance of narcissistic
illusions within the analytic relationship constitutes a fragile opportunity
for the revitalization of the self. The illusions must be cultivated, warmly
received, and certainly not challenged, allowing a reanimation of the normal
developmental process through which the illusions will eventually be
transformed, by virtue of simple exposure to reality in an emotionally
sustaining environment, into more realistic images of self and other.
Kohut stresses
throughout that he is recommending an "empathic comprehension" of
narcissistic needs and not "playacting" or "wish
fulfillment." But empathic comprehension certainly entails a receptivity
to the narcissistic illusions and an avoidance at all costs of anything which
would challenge" them or suggest that they are unrealistic. "While it
is analytically deleterious to bring about an idealization of the analyst by
artificial devices, a spontaneously occurring therapeutic mobilization of the
idealized parent imago or of the grandiose self is indeed to be welcomed and
must not be interfered with" (1971, p. 164). Kohut sees the dangers of
interference, analogous to Winnicott's notion of impingement, as very great
indeed and warns against even "slight overobjectivity of the analyst's
attitude or a coolness in the analyst's voice; or… the tendency to be jocular
with the admiring patient or to disparage the narcissistic idealization in a
humorous and kindly way" (p. 263). Anything short of warm acceptance of
narcissistic illusions concerning both the self and the analyst-which illusions
are assumed to simply express themselves, independent of the interactional
field in which the analyst participates-runs the risk of closing off the
delicate, pristine narcissistic longings and thereby eliminating the
possibility of the reemergence of healthy self development.
There is a
striking symmetry between these two different traditions of understanding
narcissistic illusions; for each, the approach of the other borders on the
lunatic. From Kohut's point of view, the kind of methodical interpretive
approach to narcissistic transferences recommended by Kernberg is extremely
counterproductive, implying a countertransferential acting out. For Kohut,
Kernberg's stance suggests great difficulty in tolerating the position in which
the narcissistic transferences place the analyst, arousing anxiety concerning
his own grandiosity (in the idealizing transference) or envy of the patient's grandiosity
(in the mirroring transference). Thus, Atwood and Stolorow argue that the oral
rage Kernberg sees in borderline patients is actually an iatrogenic consequence
of his technical approach. Methodical interpretation of the transference is
experienced by the narcissistically vulnerable patient as an assault and
generates intense narcissistic rage, which Kernberg then regards as basic and
long-standing, requiring the very procedures which created it in the first
place. From the vantage point of self psychology, Kernberg is continually
creating the monster he is perpetually slaying.
Similarly, from
the more traditional point of view, the Winnicott-Kohut approach is an exercise
in futility. An unquestioning acceptance of the patient's illusions with the
assumption that they will eventually diminish of their own accord represents a
collusion with the patient's defenses; the analytic process is thereby subverted,
and the analyst never emerges as a figure who can meaningfully help the
patient. From the traditional vantage point, the Winnicott-Kohut approach
suggests what Loewald (1973) has termed a countertransferential
"overidentification with the patient's narcissistic needs" (p. 346).
Loewald further suggests that Kohut's avoidance of any focus on "an
affirmation of the positive and enriching aspects of limitations" of self
and others constitutes a "subtle kind of seduction of the patient"
(p. 349). As Kernberg notes, unresolved narcissistic conflicts in the analyst
"may foster excessive acceptance as well as rejection of the patient's
idealization… To accept the admiration seems to be an abandonment of a neutral
position." (1975, p. 298).
Illusion as
defense, illusion as the growing edge of the self-these two approaches derive
most broadly from larger divergent perspectives on the relation between the
individual and society that have a long history in Western culture. From one
perspective (developed to its fullest by the Enlightenment philosophers of the
eighteenth century), culture and civilization humanize the individual creature,
whose personal subjectivity is beneficially renounced in favor of the higher
objectivity and rationality of society. From the other perspective (developed
to its fullest in the Romantic movement of the nineteenth century), subjective
experience is a-higher form of reality; society threatens what is most precious
in the individual, and conventional "rationality" is portrayed as an
oppressive-repressive force.
These two
approaches to illusion have generated an exciting controversy in the analytic literature,
particularly because they are dramatically contrasting and mutually exclusive
(which is often the case with competing psychoanalytic theories in their
polarized swings of the pendulum). This controversy demonstrates dramatically
the extent to which concepts like neutrality, countertransference, and empathy
are theory bound.
It is a mistake
to regard one of these approaches as more empathic than the other. They simply
proceed (empathically) from different assumptions about the patient's
experience. Kernberg's narcissist lives in an embattled world, in which he and
all others are experienced as sadistic, self-serving, and exploitative. The
only possible security lies in a devaluation of others, disarming them of their
power to hurt him. From this perspective, an empathic response entails an
appreciation of his endangered status (see Schafer, 1983) and a delineation of
his narcissistic defenses, along with an effort to make some meaningful contact
possible. To simply accept the grandiosity would be to empathize only with the
most superficial level of the patient's defenses and not with what is presumed
to be his underlying experience.
Kohut's
narcissist, on the other hand, is a brittle creature who lives in a harsh and
continually bruising world. The only possible security lies in a splitting off
of important segments of the self (either vertically or horizontally) in an
effort to protect the deep and tender feelings connected to them, often covered
over by bravado or narcissistic rage. From this perspective, an empathic
response entails an appreciation of the continual threat of self-dissolution
and disintegration, and an encouragement of growth-enhancing illusions. To
challenge the patient's illusions would be to perpetuate the repeated traumas
of childhood. With narcissistic illusions, as with most analytic phenomena,
empathy and countertransference are in the eye of the beholder.
I strongly
suspect that the majority of analysts work in neither of these two sharply
contrasting ways, that most ofus struggle to find some midpoint, undoubtedly
reflective of our own personality and style, between challenging and accepting
narcissistic illusions. Because subtlety and tone are crucial, it is difficult
to formulate such a clinical posture in simple, schematic terms. The following
description is offered as a framework for locating such an approach conceptually
and in terms of technique, within an integrated relational perspective.
The more
traditional approach to narcissism highlights the important ways in which
narcissistic illusions are used defensively, but misses their role in health
and creativity and in consolidating certain kinds of developmentally crucial
relationships with others. The developmental arrest approach has generated a
perspective on narcissism which stresses the growth-enhancing function of
narcissistic illusions, but overlooks the extent to which they often constrict
and interfere in real engagements between the analysand and other people,
including the analyst.
It is possible
to draw upon the clinical wisdom in both these contributions by viewing
narcissistic illusions in the context oftheir interactive role in perpetuating
the analysand's relational matrix. In viewing narcissism as either only
defensive or as fundamentally growth enhancing, both traditions overemphasize
what is taken to be the inherent nature of narcissistic illusions. What has
been neglected is the key function of narcissism throughout the life cycle in
perpetuating stereotyped patterns of integrating interpersonal relationships and
fantasied ties to significant objects.
An Integrated
Relational Approach
All varieties of
narcissistic illusions are generated throughout the life cycle, from the
exuberance of the toddler to the nostalgic musings of old age: grand
estimations of one's own capacities and perfection, infatuation with the
larger-than-life qualities of others whom one loves or envies, and fantasies of
an exquisite, perfect merger with desirable or dreaded others. The
determination of emotional health as opposed to psychopathology, when it comes
to narcissistic illusions, has less to do with the actual content of the
illusions than with the attitude of the individual about that content. All of
us probably experience at various times feelings and thoughts as self-ennobling
as the most grandiose narcissist, as devoted as the most star-struck idealizer,
as fused as the most boundaryless symbiosis seeker. The problem of narcissism
concerns issues of character structure, not mental content; it is not so much
what you do·and think as your attitude toward what you do and think, how
seriously you take yourself. How can this subtle issue of attitude be
conceptualized?
Consider
Nietzsche's theory of tragedy (1872/1956). Life is lived in two fundamental
dimensions, Nietzsche suggests. On the one hand, we live in a world of
illusions, continually generating transient forms and meanings with which we
play and then quickly discard. This facet of living Nietzsche terms Apollonian,
Apollo being the god of the dream, art, and illusion. On the other hand, we are
embedded in a larger unity, a universal pool of energy from which we emerge
temporarily, articulate ourselves, and into which we once again disappear. This
facet of living Nietzsche terms Dionysian, Dionysus representing reimmersion in
this undifferentiated oneness and, in Nietzsche's system, the inevitable
undoing of all illusions, all individual existence.
Nietzsche
establishes "the tragic" as the fullest, richest model of living, and
the truly tragic represents a balance between the Apollonian and Dionysian
dimensions. The tragic man (this phrase must be disentangled from all
pejorative connotations) is one who is able to fully pursue his Apollonian
illusions and also is able to relinquish them in the face of the inevitable
realities of the human condition. The tragic man regards his life as a work of
art, to be conceived, shaped, polished, and inevitably dissolved. The
prototypical tragic activity is play, in which new forms are continually
created and demolished, in which the individuality of the player is continually
articulated, developed, and relinquished. In the passage used as the epigraph
for this chapter, Nietzsche uses the building of sandcastles as a metaphor for
the dialectic he envisions as the underlying structure of life and the essence
of the tragic.
Picture the
beach at low tide. Three different approaches are possible. The Apollonian man
builds elaborate sandcastles, throwing himself into his activity as if his
creations would last forever, totally oblivious to the incoming tide which will
demolish his productions. Here is someone who ignores reality and is therefore
continually surprised, battered, and bruised by it. The Dionysian man sees the
inevitability of the leveling tide and therefore builds no castles. His
constant preoccupation with the ephemeral nature of his life and his creations
allows him no psychic space in which to live and play. He will only build if
his productions are assured of immortality, but unlike the Apollonian man, he
suffers no delusions in this regard. Here is someone tyrannized and depleted by
reality.
The third option
is Nietzsche's tragic man, aware of the tide and the transitory nature of his
productions, yet building his sandcastles nevertheless. The inevitable
limitations of reality do not dim the passion with which he builds his castles;
in fact, the inexorable realities add a poignancy and sweetness to his passion.
The tragicomic play in which our third man builds, Nietzsche suggests, is the
richest form of life, generating the deepest meaning from the dialectical
interplay of illusion and reality.
The very word
"illusion," Loewald (1974, p. 354) reminds us, derives from the Latin
“ludere”, to play. Healthy narcissism reflects Nietzsche's subtle dialectical
balance between illusions and reality; illusions concerning oneself and others
are generated, playfully enjoyed, and relinquished in the face of disappointments.
New illusions are continually created and dissolved. Winnicott (1971) has described
the important connections between healthy illusion, play, creativity, and cultural
phenomena in general.
In pathological
narcissism, on the other hand, illusions are taken too seriously, insisted
upon. In some narcissistic disturbances, illusions are actively and consciously
maintained; reality is sacrificed in order to perpetuate an addictive devotion
to self-ennobling, idealizing, or symbiotic fictions. This is the approach of the
first man on the beach, blindly building and building. In some narcissistic
disturbances, illusions are harbored secretly or repressed; preoccupation with
the limitations and risks of reality lead to an absence of joyfulness or
liveliness - even a paralysis. Any activity is threatening because it
inevitably encounters limitations, and these are felt to be unacceptable. This
is the approach of the second man on the beach, holding out for immortality and
waiting in despair for the tide.
What is the
etiology ofsuch disturbances? What determines whether one will be able to
negotiate the delicate balance between illusions and reality in healthy
narcissism, or whether one will suffer an addictive devotion to illusions
resulting in either a removal from reality or a despair in the face of it? The
key factor resides in the interplay of illusions and reality in the
character-forming relationships with significant others. What is crucial, therefore,
is the interactive function of illusions within the analysand's relational
matrix.
The growth of the balance necessary for healthy
narcissism requires a particular sort of relationship with a parent, in which
the parent is able to comfortably experience both the child and herself in both
modes, in playful illusions of grandiosity, idealization, and fusion, and in
deflating disappointments and realistic limitations. The child naturally and
playfully generates lofty self-overvaluations, glowing overvaluations of the parent,
and boundaryless experiences of sameness and fusion. The ideal parental
response to these experiences consists in a participation coupled with the
capacity to disengage, a capacity to enjoy and play with the child's illusions,
to add illusions of his or her own, and to let the illusions go, experiencing
the child and herself in more realistic terms. Thus, the parent participates
with the child in requisite experiences characterized by shifting idealization
and aggrandizements - now the child is elevated, now the parent, now both
together. The ideal parental
response is neither a total immersion in illusion nor a cynical rationalism,
but a capacity to play with illusions while never losing sight of the fact that
this is a form of play Consider the position of the child in relation to a
parent who, in one way or another, takes these kinds of illusions extremely
seriously, whose own sense of security in fact is contingent upon them. Such a
parent insists on specific overvaluations of the child or herself or both.
These illusions have become addictive for the parent, and they become a dominant
feature in the possibilities for relatedness which such a parent offers the
child. The more addictive the illusions for the parent, the more unavoidable
they become for the child, who feels that the only way to connect with the
parent, to be engaged with him, is to participate in his illusions. Such a
child must regard himself as perfect and extraordinary and be seen by the
parent that way, to be seen at all; or he must worship the parent as perfect
and extraordinary to become real and important to the parent. Further, children
tend to pick up how crucial such illusions are for the parent's shaky sense of self-esteem.
Deutsch (1937) long ago noted the role of parental "induction" in
cases of "folie-à-deux," where adoption by the child of the parent's
delusion represents "an important part of an attempt to rescue the object
through identification with it, or its delusional system" (p. 247).
Abandonment of parental illusions thus becomes an emotional equivalent of
abandonment of the parents themselves, the avoidance of which, as M. Friedman
(1985) has argued, is an underlying feature in many forms of psychopathology.
In such
circumstances, sustaining parental illusions becomes the basis for stability
and for maintaining connections with others, the vehicle for what Fairbairn
repeatedly terms the "tie to bad objects," or what Robbins (1982)
more recently has described as pathological efforts at symbiotic bonding. Here
illusions are no longer the spontaneously generated, transitory, playful
creation of an active mind. Illusions are insisted upon with utmost seriousness
by significant others, and they become the necessary price for contact and
relation. Ogden (1982) speaks of
<
the ever-present threat that if the infant fails to comply, he
would cease to exist for the mother. This threat is the muscle behind the
demand for compliance: "If you are not what I need you to be, you don't
exist for me." Or in other language, "I can see in you only what I
put there. If I don't see that, I see nothing.">> (p. 16)
This is true not
just of infancy, but throughout childhood and later into adulthood. Every
analyst is familiar with the dread adult patients frequently feel in connection
with major characterological change; they anticipate a profound sense of isolation
from parents (alive or dead) who related to them, seemed to need so much to
relate to them, only through their now-loosened and about-to-be-transcended
character pathology (see Searles, 1958).
The mithological
figure of Icarus vividly captures the powerful relationship between the child
and the parent's illusions. Daedalus, the builder of the Labyrinth, constructs
wings of feathers and wax, so that he and his son Icarus can escape their
island prison. The use of such wings requires a true sense of Nietzsche's dialectical
balance: flying too high risks a melting of the wings by the sun; flying too
low risks a weighing down of the wings from the dampness of the ocean. Icarus does
not heed the warning he receives. He flies too close to the sun; his wings
melt, and he plunges into the ocean, disappearing beneath a clump of floating
feathers.
We have all been
born of imperfect parents, with favorite illusions about themselves and their
progeny buoying their self-esteem, cherished along a continuum ending with
addiction to illusion. We have all come to know ourselves through participation
in parental illusions, which have become our own. Like Icarus, therefore, we
have all donned Daedalus' wings. It is the subtleties of parental involvement
with these illusions which greatly influence the nature of the flight provided by
those wings-whether one can fly high enough to enjoy them and truly soar, or
whether the sense of ponderous necessity concerning the illusions leads one to
fly too high or to never leave the ground.
The myth of
Icarus points to another significant feature of generational interaction in the
subtleties of narcissistic illusion. In most accounts Daedalus is portrayed as
a caring father, at least in his warnings to Icarus to fly neither too high nor
too low, and Daedalus himself is able to negotiate a successful flight to safety.
Children of illustrious parents are particularly prone to narcissistic
difficulties. With parents of distinction of one sort or another, it takes particular
sensitivity to be able to help a child sort through and digest parental
identifications to generate illusions and ambitions of his or her own.
In both prior
approaches to narcissism, pathological grandiosity and pathological
idealization are understood largely as forces operating within the internal
psychic economy of the individual. They are viewed as internally generated
phenomena, either as defensive solutions to anxiety, frustration, and envy, or
as spontaneously arising, pristine, early developmental needs. The developmental-arrest
approach suffers from this constraint just as much as the more traditional
approach. Illusion is treated not as a normal product of mental activity
throughout the life cycle, but is located within the earliest developmental
phases. And illusions within the psychoanalytic situation are treated as
reflective of the early developmental needs, in pure form, rather than as
learned modes of connection with others, as the not-at-all-playful,
stereotyped, compulsive patterns of integration they have become.
Ever since
Freud's abandonment of the theory of infantile seduction, the legacy of drive
theory for the subsequent history of psychoanalytic ideas has included an
underemphasis of the role of actual relationships in the evolution of mental
structures and content, and of the residues of actual interactions in fantasied
object ties. With respect to narcissism, both traditions isolate the figure
within the relational tapestry. In so doing, they overlook the extent to which
grandiosity and idealization function as interactional modes, arising as learned
patterns of integrating relationships, and maintained as the vehicle for
intimate connections (real and imagined) with others. They focus on one
dimension of the relational matrix, the self, but not on the self with others;
to regard these phenomena solely in terms of self-organization is like working
with only half the pieces of a jigsaw puzzle.
The major
theorists we have been considering do not completely fail to notice these
interactional facets of narcissistic phenomena. They are too astute as
clinicians to do so. The problem is that the specifics of parental character
and fantasied object ties do not fit into theoretical models emphasizing what
are taken to be spontaneously arising, developmental phenomena, so they are
noticed clinically and then passed over when major etiological dynamics are assigned
or technical approaches developed. The subtleties of the parents' personalities,
the ways in which they required the child to maintain narcissistic illusions,
are lost; the parents are viewed in a binary fashion, either as gratifying or
not gratifying infantile needs (drives or relational).
Freud's paper
"On Narcissism," for example, contains a wry and incisive description
of parents' narcissistic investment in their children:
“If we look at
the attitude of affectionate parents towards their children, we have to
recognize that 'it isa revival and reproduction of their own narcissism, which
they have long since abandoned… They are under a compulsion to ascribe every
perfection to the child - which sober observation would find no occasion to do -
and to conceal and forget all his shortcomings… They are inclined to suspend in
the child's favor the operation of all the cultural acquisitions which their own
narcissism has been forced to respect, and to renew on his behalf the claims to
privileges which were long ago given up by themselves… The child shall fulfill
those wishful dreams of the parents which they never carried out-the boy shall
become a great man and a hero in his father's place, and the girl shall marry a
prince as a tardy compensation for her mother. At the most touchy point in the narcissistic
system, the immortality of the ego, which is so hard pressed by reality, security
is achieved by taking refuge in the child. Parental love, which is so moving
and at bottom so childish, is nothing but the parents' narcissism born again.”
(1914b, pp. 90-91)
Freud calls our
attention to the striking similarity between the parents' attitude toward the
child and the child's attitude toward himself. The parent overvalues the child;
the child overvalues himself. Freud does not, however, derive the child's narcissism
from the parents' attitude! He points to the parents' often-compulsive need to
use the child as a magic solution for their own limitations and
disappointments. Yet he does not consider how such a set of parental
expectations and needs might contribute to the child's sense of who he is and
who he needs to be for others. Although parental values, internalized in the
ego ideal, become important later on in recapturing the primary narcissistic
experience, Freud derives infantile narcissism from the inherent properties of self-directed
libido. Infantile grandiosity is an instinctual vicissitude; self-love
generates narcissism, apart from the relational matrix. In effect, Freud
derives the parents' narcissism from the child's, their own unresolved infantile
narcissistic longings and the opportunity provided by their child's infantile
narcissism to evoke their own. In viewing narcissism as a quality inherent in
self-directed libido, Freud underplays the extent to which parental fantasies
influence the child's sense of who he is and has to be for the parents.
Infantile experience shapes adult character, and adult character through
parenting shapes infantile experience, in a continually evolving generational
cycle within the relational matrix. Kernberg similarly provides a vivid portrait
of parental narcissism at work in the dynamic interactions within families
producing children with later narcissistic difficulties.
Their histories reveal that each patient possessed some inherent quality which could have objectively aroused the envy or admiration ofothers. Forexample, unusual physical attractiveness or some special talent became a refuge against the basic feelings of being unloved and of being the objects of revengeful hatred. Sometimes it was rather the cold hostile mother's narcissistic use of the child which made him "special," set him off on the road in a search for compensatory admiration and greatness, and fostered the characterological defense of spiteful devaluation of others. For example, two patients were used by their mothers as a kind of "object of art," being dressed up and exposed to public admiration in an almost grotesque way, so that fantasies of power and greatness linked with exhibitionistic trends became central in their compensatory efforts against oral rage and envy. These patients often occupy a pivotal point in their family structure, such as being the only child, or the only "brilliant" child, or the one who is supposed to fulfill the family aspirations.(1975, pp. 234-235)
How could a
child growing up in such circumstances become anything but narcissistic? become
visible to his parents in any form other than as an extraordinary, larger-than-life
creature? Why the need to evoke a hypothetical excess of aggression (either
constitutional or based on great deprivation in the earliest years) to account
for what is more simply and clearly derivable from the relational matrix? Like
Freud, Kernberg sees the clinical relevance of parental values and
expectations, the constricted forms of relationships they offer to the child;
yet this factor is assigned only a peripheral etiological role in shaping later
defenses against early conflicts. Kernberg's model of mind, still drawing strongly
on the monadic framework of drive theory, regards pathological narcissism as an
internally generated mechanism, established in the first years of life in the
face of extreme oral rage. The mother is important, not in the subtleties of
her character and the particularities of the relational patterns she offers the
child, but in her gross role as frustrator of the child's oral needs and as an
object for the child's oral rage.
Kohut's clinical
reports reflect a similar striking discordance between rich observations of parent-child
interactions and a theoretical model of narcissism which assigns the particular
content of these interactions to a secondary role. Kohut describes patients who
exhibit various forms of grandiosity, some noisily proclaimed, others secretly
and shamefully harbored. Kohut considers these to be manifestations of
"archaic" grandiosity, which was not allowed to establish itself and
undergo normal transmuting internalization because of the parents' failures as
self-objects. Thus, his model derives narcissism from the expression of
inherent sources. Yet, Kohut often informs us (usually parenthetically) that
the parents failed the child in quite specific ways, using that child as a
narcissistic extension of themselves in precisely the manner in which the child
then constructs his grandiosity.
Within both
traditions there has been movement toward granting greater etiological
importance to parental character and the specifics of child-parent
interactions. From the drive-theory side, Rothstein (1984) has placed
increasing emphasis on the role of the actual relationship in the generation
and maintenance of narcissistic illusion, and Robbins (1982) has written of the
ways in which narcissistic phenomena operate as shared illusions, drawing on
grandiose fantasies of idealized objects. From the relational-model side, there
has been discussion of the parents, not simply in terms of their failure to provide
self-object functions for the child, but also in terms of their use of the
child as their own self-object (Atwood and Stolorow, 1984).
I have suggested
that in ideal parenting the parent participates with the child in a variable
fashion that contains both joyful play with illusions and an affirming embrace
of reality. Loewald has depicted the delicate interpenetrability between illusion
and consensual reality that can develop from such interactions in a redefinition
of the traditional concept of reality testing:
“Reality testing
is far more than an intellectual or cognitive function. It may be understood
more comprehensively as the experiential testing of fantasy - its potential and
suitability for actualization - and the testing of actuality - its potential
for encompassing it in, and penetrating it with, one's fantasy life. We deal
with the task of a reciprocal transposition.” (1974, p. 368)
How does the
analyst help the analysand arrive at such a balance between illusion and
reality, at the capacity to live in and fuse both realms? Loewald suggests that
the analyst's interpretations and demeanor convey a subtle double quality which
makes this possible. On the one hand, the analyst's descriptions and
interpretations enable the patient to advance his access to his own subjectivity
and inner resources. On the other hand,
“There may be at
times, in addition, that other quality to the analyst's communication, difficult
to describe, which mediates another dimension to the patient's experiences,
raising them to a higher, more comprehensively human level of integration and
validity while also signaling the transitory nature of human experience.”
(1974, p. 356)
Comentarii